Even the Jesuit missionary
Robert de Nobili, whom Francis X. Clooney ("Hindu God, Christian
God. How Reason Helps Break Down the Boundaries between Religions",
Oxford 2001), somewhat distastefully in my opinion, presents as a
sort of model for "interreligious theological conversation",
asked: "Who could ever doubt that there is a Sovereign Lord of
all things who is at the same time their ultimate cause?" Many,
of course, have doubted this, or thought that the "Sovereign
Lord" is not also the "ultimate cause", or that there
is no one cause. My point, however, is that even those people who
agree that there is "a Sovereign Lord" do not, by
this agreement, assent to a belief in the same entity. Easily they
could doubt that there is the Sovereign Lord whose name is God and whom de Nobili professed.
It is true enough that
they can on the basis of their agreement have a debate about the Sovereign Lord.
"The Sovereign Lord is great," one of the agreers may say,
and the other may reply, "No, the Sovereign Lord is without
size." But do they differ because they have variant opinions
about the same entity, or because they consider different entities as
the Sovereign Lord? If their cosmologies differ sufficiently, it will
even become pointless to ask this question, because, except from a
privileged position (i.e. the worldview of the one making the judgement), there is
no way to judge which the actual entities they are talking
about are. So, significantly, they are talking about some entity qua
"Sovereign Lord", with the entity's identity neither
central nor easy to establish.
Take
it, for example, that both are talking about the god Śiva. In that
case, it seems clear that, if the entity exists, one of them is more
correct in his account of it. But the first agreer might
counter, "What is without size is not Śiva." In that case,
from the first agreer's point of view, they are talking about
different entities, one Śiva and the other without size; from the
second's, they are talking about the same entity, but one of them has
a defective understanding of it. There are not just the levels of
real entities, on the one hand, and descriptions, on the other, but
also an intermediate one, where the mapping of descriptions to
entities is negotiated; and the picture is further complicated because
the real entities are not immediately accessible, but must be assumed
and described, so that descriptions are effectively mapped onto other
descriptions.
Or take it that they are
talking about two different gods, and shift their conversation
to this topic. "Śiva is the Sovereign Lord," says the
first, and the second, "No, Viṣṇu is the Sovereign
Lord." A third agreer will object to their disagreement and tell
them that they are referring to the same god, Harihara,
by different name; the next will differ slightly, saying that the
difference between Śiva and Viṣṇu is real enough, yet they are
both aspects of Harihara. Now the first agreer may say, "I
disagree. Śiva is the
Sovereign Lord, and Viṣṇu is inferior to him." The
second agreer will say the opposite. Another Hindu who has listened
to the whole conversation might think, for one reason or another,
that arguing about which god is greater is pointless; so might a
Buddhist, who thinks that any Bodhisattva
is greater than the gods anyway; while a Christian might sum up the
whole discussion as "They disagree about the name of God."
None of these viewpoints
is wholly satisfactory when it is transferred into academic
discourse, but it is the last (perhaps merely because it is so
exceptionally widespread and under-critiqued) that I find
particularly objectionable. It simply does not do to erase the very
real differences between different conceptions of deity, and the way
that these conceptions depend on the wider cosmological assumptions
one makes, by talking about God, capital G, as if everyone already
understood what this meant, irrespective of their worldview. We
cannot, in other words, take for granted "God" while people
are still disagreeing about gods.
Well, let us imagine the
Christian agreer a little more charitably. He will say, "They
disagree about the nature of God," and if we ask why he inserts
this Western term, no definite article, capital G and all, into a
discussion about Hindu theology, he will say that it is a shorthand.
He means nothing more than "Sovereign Lord", and his
sentence, more fully, was intended to mean "They disagree about
the nature of the deity whom they consider to be the Sovereign Lord,"
leaving open the possibility of all the responses we saw above.
That does not change the
fact that the usage is problematic. It is ambiguous at best, and it
leads to such non sequiturs as the following: Clooney defines
theology rather broadly as "people scrutiniz[ing] their own
faith traditions with an eye toward understanding (and then living)
that faith more adequately", but then wants to "initiat[e]
an extended conversation between the Hindu and Christian theological
traditions on four topis: God's existence, the true God, divine
embodiment, and the measuring of religions by revelation." It
surely does not due to lead into the topic by making the acceptance
of a capital G God, meaning "Supreme Lord"-cum-"ultimate
cause", the basis for theological dialogue.
Firstly, it erases several
questions that would occur to modern Hindus but rarely to modern
Christians: Are there any gods (devas)?
Is there any one god ruling all things? Is there an ultimate cause of
all things? Is it a god? Is this god the same as the god ruling all
things? Is this god qualitatively different from other gods? Is this
deity, the Īśvara
(Lord) what Christians mean by God? Are the devas perhaps not gods,
but rather angels? Is the Īśvara
God, but not at all a god, one (even if supreme) among many, in the
polytheistic sense? Are there perhaps no devas?
The way that Clooney
frames the discussion, the first three questions are conflated into
"Does God exist?", or perhaps, just a hint more neutrally,
"Is there a God?" It is taken for granted that God is not a
member of the same class as the other devas, that their existence is
not an important issue, that their nature not an interesting
question, and that the question of a supreme god is only relevant if
it is simultaneously about the ultimate cause. Hardly a basis for
interfaith work that leads one to expect much in the way of results,
or much of an opening to new perspectives differing from Western
presumptions.
In my opinion, it is the
Christian conflation of (1) the concept of deity or "god"
with (2) the specific properties of the single god of Monotheism1
and (3) "God" as a personal name that makes Clooney go from
the question considered in chapter 2 of his book, "Is there a
God[?]", to the topic of chapter 3, "conclusions about who
God is" rather than, e.g., "conclusions about who is God";
the latter I would more fully construe as "... who is the person
that has the properties qualifying them as God" (=Supreme Lord
and ultimate cause of all things), the former as "what is the
name and what are the properties of the entity God2".
Indeed, he summarizes the
sorts of heliefs treated in chapter 2 as "there is a God"
and "there is one God" (although, of course, starting with
questions about a capital-G God, the unity and uniqueness of this God
is already taken for granted), and those of chapter 3 as: "this
is God's name." The most honest summary comes just a few lines
later: "questions about whether there is a God and what God is
like". Thus the meaning of "god" is limited to a
single and ultimate being by being restricted to "God", and
the polytheistic (or, to already pander to those who would exclude an
Īśvara from the number
of devas, the polydevistic) context in which such a concept is
embedded in India is disregarded from the start. If the discussion is
framed as one about God and his properties, the many disagreements
people could have about the "Sovereign Lord" (as we saw
above) will be hard to account for, and seem somehow extraneous to
the discussion. Yet Clooney does not intimate that he is knowingly
leaving polytheistic positions out: "Hindu God, Christian God
focusses rather narrowly on how Christian and Hindu theologians
reason theologically, discern, assert, and defend the truth, and aim
to persuade both insiders and outsiders of that truth." The
actual topic is rather narrower, as Clooney does not fathom
polytheism as methodology3, as would behoove any
comparative theologian.
Now, it must be granted
that Clooney can sometimes be more nuanced, as when he describes the
Hindu school of philosophy, Mimamsa:
"The
Mīmāṃsā
theologians worked with a simple, realistic world view and were
willing to acknowledge the gods as legitimate recipients of worship
and invocation. But since it suffices for ritual purposes to assert
that the gods can be invoked, they also felt that there was no need
to speculate further about the nature of these gods. While Mīmāṃsā
is not antitheistic, it has no need for the postulate of a Supreme
Being, Lord, or Creator. On the whole, ordinary reasoning about any
religious topic must defer to the logic of ritual obligation and the
world it implies."
The use of antitheistic in
place of the simpler atheistic seems somewhat obscurantist to me, but
otherwise, this is a fair account of what are in fact often described
as atheists (on Wikipedia, prominently) because they are do not
suscribe to Theism in the peculiar sense that word has in Western
descriptions of Hindu philosophy, namely "the belief that
Sovereign Lord and ultimate cause are one and should be worshipped";
notably, the usage does not fit well with the usual usage of theism,
or categories like monotheism, atheism, polytheism (vague and of
little analytical use as they are), but ties in well with the sort of
use of "God" that I just criticized Clooney for.
It is therefore a systemic
problem of intellectual erasure that I am arguing against, and thus
even the better passages in the book do not save him from the
criticism that he has led into his book (I have been quoting from
chapter 1 only so far) with far more Christian bias than he accounts
for in his long reflections on writing a theological work about Hindu
theology as a Christian.
This trend continues
throughout the book; thus he says that "[i]n the beginning, at
least, Vaiśeṣika thinkers
had no need for God as an intellectual principle." This leaves
open the rather important question of whether they accepted or
presumed the existence of non-capitalized gods.
After the Vaiśeṣika,
Clooney treats the Nyayas, in particular their oldest text, the Nyāya
Sūtras, citing the one passage dealing with "God":
"IV.1.19
The Lord is the cause, since we see that human action lacks results.
IV.1.20
This is not so since, as a matter of fact, no result is accomplished
without human action.
IV.1.21
Since that is efficacious, the reason lacks force."
He
comments that the passage "is most probably also a rejection of
the need for a God intended to guarantee the efficacy of human
activity. Since human action can be explained without positing God,
it is wise to avoid this superfluous postulate." In that sense,
it "reads as a criticism of the postulation of theism4".
This is of course the theism of Western Indology; it does not mean
belief in gods. In fact the author of the Sūtras may very
well have taken the existence of gods for granted, even if it is
likely that they reject an Īśvara,
or Lord.
It is strange that Clooney
does not here, where he first cites an actual piece of Indian
theology, or at any previous point discuss what Indian words and
concepts he sees fit to translate as God. We can see that Īśvara
is one of them.
Of the first later
Nyāya writer he discusses, Annambhaṭṭa, it suffices to say that
presenting his arguments for the existence of a creator god without
giving an account of his wider theology, his opinions about devas, is
unhelpful; where are they to be situated in his system? Are they
īśvara or finite self? Clooney labels the latter as human and
translates the former as "the lord", leaving no room for
beings like devas, asuras, and the like. Did Annambhaṭṭa consider
these to be finite selfs, did he not believe in them at all, or does
he in fact mean īśvara in a generic sense
(Sanskrit has no definite article, after all)?
When he paraphrases
Jayanta4
(also a Nyāya)
with "We name this maker 'God.'" it would be incumbent on
him
to give us the word he is translating here. From a stray reference
later, it is presumably Īśvara.
By this, he meant
Śiva, and he also worshipped Śiva's
wife Pārvatī and their child Gaṇeśa,
and mentions other "gods [devas] and demons [asuras]" and
"Brahmā | The Creator God" (a rather confusing gloss when
Īśvara,
God, and creator
god are elsewhere taken as synonymous). What status do these other
gods have for him? Is Śiva a god like them?
Among those opposed to the
arguments for "God", Clooney introduces the Buddhists as
"religiously nontheistic: not God but the Buddha is the sole and
sufficient source of religious wisdom." This is surely
misleading on several counts—Buddhists believe in and (may) worship gods
(devas), and they also worship that "source of religious
wisdom", the Buddha, making him eligible as a god or God if this
is really to be used as an analytical term. Unless one discounts all
devotional rituals in Buddhism as non-religious because they are
subordinated to the quest for Nirvana (of course, they can also be
part of that quest!), which seems absurd, this description is
incorrect. Why not describe the Buddhist position explicitly, which
would require more words, than using categories like "religiously
nontheistic", which seem precise and analytical, but are in fact
vague and ill-fitting?
The real difference
of Indian theological debate from Western ones is completely hidden
through all these terminological choices. The debate between Nyāya
logicians, Buddhists and Mīmāṃsins
is not about deity but about the specific question of a creator god6,
which is only one aspect of the "question of God" in the
West. There, the question of uniqueness has been tied inextricably to
the exclusive fitness as an object worship. And it is largely this
that the capital G enshrines: because there is only one god, God, it
is a name, not just a description. And that name inherently includes
an aspect not central to the interschool debates in India at all: the
exclusive fitness as an object of worship. So the sentence
"Is there is a God?", because of the many conflations that
obtain in a Christian/Western context, would need to be broken up
into the two questions, "Are there devas?" and "Is
there an Īśvara?" The assertion "There is one
God" has strong implicitations for religious practice, while
"There is one Īśvara" does not necessarily have them.
From the fact that Jayanta argues for the unity of the Īśvara,
it also seems that a multiplicity of
them is not implausible per se,
while in the West, the question "Is there a God?" already
precludes the possibility of more than one entity that is a God,
because a capital-G God is by definition unique.
If nothing else, we have
gained some understanding of the sort of presumptions and
terminological sleights-of-hand that lead to people calling
polytheists either atheists or monotheists, and inventing definitions
of polytheism that describe the belief system of absolutely no
one.
I will continue the
discussion of Clooney's book in two other posts, on Brahman
understood as "God" and on the concept of Īśvara.
Notes
1: I use "Monotheism"
as a historical category referring specifically to those traditions
that stand in some historical continuity to the Hebrew Bible, as, in
keeping with my opinion that the meaning of a concept—like the idea
of a single, unique god—is dependent for its meaning on its
context, and so it is not useful to apply the label to superficially
similar beliefs, which will tend to lack certain features that are
typical of Monotheism, e.g. the idea that belief in or worship of
multiple deities is ethically objectionable.
2: As noted before, this
takes the entity God for granted, rather than, so to speak,
the position of God, whose nature depends on the cosmology one
adopts, and which is filled by an entity whose identity is up for
debate. At the danger of oversimplifying, there is some sense in
saying that the Christian God is a conflation of person and function,
whereas in some other traditions (e.g. the Greek), the who of
the person and the what of the function are distinct. Of
course the distinction breaks down in many areas (as, e.g., Atlas'
identity is fundamentally associated with his function), but most
discussion of, e.g., the demiurge, or, in post-Stoic philosophy, "the
god" (more usually translated "God", of course),
meaning effectively "Sovereign Lord" and highest
principle (which can, but need not, mean "ultimate cause"),
with the stress on the latter, discusses them qua demiurge, or
qua "the god".
Galen, for example, believed that there was a demiurge or creator
(function), but was uncertain about whether he was Zeus (person).
3: For a defense of
methodological polytheism, see Edward Butler, "Polytheism
as Methodology in the Study of Religions". My objection to that
article would be that it throws out the methodologically agnostic
baby (which goes unmentioned) with the methodologically atheist
bathwater.
4: No better or worse is
the previous description that "(Nyaya)'s primary text, the
(Nyaya Sutras) of Gautama, can be read as a neutral analysis neither
favoring nor opposing the idea of God."
5: At least in this case,
we are told that Jayanta argues against the possibility of multiple
creator gods. But yet again, whether a rejection of "multiple
'Gods'" (the scare quotes seem to signify a feeling of complete
incoherence of the phrase) is also a rejection of multiple gods is
not explained, and would probably be assumed by most readers if no
discussion of his Śaivism
and mention of other gods followed.
6: The "Sovereign
Lord" part of the concept of Īśvara
is thus incidental; in
fact, Buddhists may see Buddhas and Bodhisattvas as "Sovereign
Lords of all things", and also accepts a hierarchy of gods and
thus a "Sovereign Lord" of gods.
Keine Kommentare:
Kommentar veröffentlichen